Lunsford and Ede’s distinctions—and overlaps—between
classical and modern rhetoric are helpful in coming toward a (more helpful and
unified) definition of rhetoric, one that brings attention to the presence of
classical rhetoric (particularly Aristotle) in modern theories of
rhetoric. By divorcing Aristotle’s Rhetoric from his full body of work, contemporary
theorists of rhetoric tend to misrepresent and misinterpret Aristotle’s goal of
rhetoric to the point where Aristotle’s and other classical rhetoricians’
theories of rhetoric are deemed obsolete for a modern context; Lunsford and
Ede—and Zappan—demonstrate that theories of rhetoric from classical
rhetoricians—Aristotle in particular—are still useful lenses to analyze
language use in current, contemporary contexts.
As Lunsford and Ede explain, Aristotle was interested in how
the rhetor and audience negotiate meaning: “Aristotle’s rhetoric provides a
complete description of the dynamic interaction between rhetor and audience, an
interaction mediated by language” (44).
Meaning-making is then an interactive process—a social interaction that
is negotiated with language. This
social, dialogic interaction that’s involved in creating meaning has often been
attributed to modern rhetoricians such as Bhaktin and Burke—in our class
specifically. Lunsford and Ede go as far
as to point out how Burke explicitly ties persuasion (in the broader sense),
identification, and communication—Burke uses Aristotle’s conceptualization of
rhetoric to contextualize it within the evolving contexts of the time.
I think that might be my “take-away” from the readings this
week—well, I think there’s a few. First, as Lunsford and Ede explain, we—as
contemporary rhetoricians—shouldn’t “throw the baby out with the bathwater.” In
other words, Aristotle and the other classics have something to offer; their
theories are not wholly obsolete in the changing contemporary contexts. The second “take-away” is closely tie to the
first: just as Burke and Zappan, we should take the essence of Aristotle
(through his full body of work) and contextualize it. As Zappan points out: “dialogue—conceived not
as a mode of persuasion, but as a testing of one’s own ideas, a contesting of
others’ ideas, and a collaborative creating of ideas—is possible in any medium:
oral, print, digital” (320-1). I liked
this excerpt particularly because Zappan is not fashioning the Digital
environment as a wholly unique and different point of study; with the emergence
(and ever-emergence) of digital environemnts and digital communities, the
digital is still a medium of communication where dialogue takes place. While
the digital environment is, in fact, unique and different, it is not wholly
unique as to “throw the baby out with the bathwater.” Understood fairly, Aristotle speaks about
dialogue and negotiation of meaning—what better place for this to occur than in
digital environments? But as Zappan
points out, we should contextualize Aristotle’s conceptualization of rhetoric
to account for the affordances and constraints of the digital forum: speed,
reach, anonymity, and interactivity.
No comments:
Post a Comment