Monday, April 15, 2013

Old Rhetoric Vs. New Rhetoric


Pointing out the inaccuracy of four typically accepted distinctions between classical and modern rhetoric, Andrea Lunsford and Lisa Ede put forward three different distinctions between classical and modern rhetoric, which are interestingly based on three similarities between classical and modern rhetoric they value.

Their article is undoubtedly thought-provoking. However, their distinctions also seem simplified. As their discussion centers on Aristotle (“because the Aristotelian theory is the most complete of all classical rhetorics” (40)), my first question is to what extent can Aristotle represent the classical rhetoric. Admittedly, Aristotle is very influential and his systematic theory lays the foundation for the long tradition of rhetoric. But when one of Lunsford and Ede’s distinctions is based on Aristotle’s concept of knowledge, whether Aristotle’s theory alone can represent classical rhetoric becomes a question. According to Lunsford and Ede, one difference between classical and modern rhetoric lies in that in Aristotle’s world, knowledge results in clarity and certainty (“rhetor and audience come into a state of knowing which places them in a clearly defined relationship with the world and with each other”) while for modern rhetoric the nature of knowledge itself is questionable – knowing is never objective, always based on a human perspective (47). Moreover, in Aristotle’s system, there are two types of knowledge – knowledge of the necessary and knowledge of the contingent, and for Aristotle “Rhetoric’s realm is limited to the contingent” (47). Thus, Lunsford and Ede’s second distinction between classical and modern rhetoric is based on Aristotle’s rhetoric related to knowledge of the contingent, which I am afraid would not justly reflect classical rhetoric. Anyone familiar with Plato who is also very influential and echoed by Weaver later, would remember that for Plato rhetoric is a means to pursue real truth and absolute knowledge and though some people (like philosophers) can remember absolute knowledge they knew before in heaven, some other people fail. For Plato, rhetoric is also “the art of persuasion” (157), but it is a very different type of persuasion that “leads the soul by means of words” (156). In this sense, it might not be fair to equate Aristotle with classical rhetoric.

On the second place, Lunsford and Ede’s distinctions also seem ambiguous. Their first distinction is based on the similarity that “Both classical and modern rhetoric view man as a language-using animal” (45). Lunsford and Ede believe Aristotle’s works “indicate that Aristotle was aware of man’s ability to use symbols and that he viewed language as the medium through which judgment about the world are communicated” (45). Though in Rhetoric Aristotle talks about style and metaphor, language is not the focus of his rhetoric. And considering scholars such as Richards, Gates, and Bakhtin who analyze language in depth, it is difficult to say Aristotle’s awareness of symbol-using and language as the medium is comparable to the works of modern rhetoric. A major difference between classical and modern rhetoric, in my view, lies in modern rhetoric’s examination of language and its role in generating knowledge. While Lunsford and Ede stress viewing “man as a language-using animal” (45) as the similarity between classical and modern rhetoric and blur their difference, the importance of their corresponding distinction remains unexplained. They claim that “Aristotle addresses himself primarily to the oral use of language; our is primarily an age of print” (45). In Aristotle’s time, writing was still a new technology and he focused on speaking. We may say this distinction is primarily because of the limit of historical conditions. If Aristotle were born much later, he might have created a very different system of rhetoric. But what does this distinction mean? Why is it important? How is this related to the study of language? Does modern rhetoric simply ignore speech? How has an emphasis on written discourse shaped our understanding of rhetoric? Lunsford and Ede believe that this distinction is “potentially profound” (46) but refuse to explain why by stating that “Our understanding of the historical and methodological ramifications of the speaking/ writing distinction has been hampered by the twentieth-century split among speech, linguistics, philosophy, and English departments” (46). They indeed found an important fact, but without explanation, the meaning of this distinction remains ambiguous.

Similarly, before discussing the second distinction, Lunsford and Ede point out the second similarity that “rhetor and audience may jointly have access to knowledge” (45), which blurs another important difference that their second distinction avoids addressing. The word “jointly” makes the relationship between rhetor and audience rather ambiguous. In classical rhetoric, it is easier to find a hierarchy – a rhetor can be intellectually or morally better than the audience. Plato’s Phaedrus depicts Socrates as a wise man who skillfully guides a passive, obedient listener. Aristotle’s rhetor should receive good training while the audience are “untrained thinkers” (183). Quintilian believes a “good man speaking well” (8). Also, classical rhetoric is not open to every citizen. In modern rhetoric, not only is the nature of knowledge questioned, but the relationship between rhetor and audience is changed. Foucault reveals the social structure and power relations in discourse as well as ideologies existing in knowledge, giving both rhetor and audience the opportunity to realize and change their positions. Bakhtin emphasizes dialogue, which allows the rhetor and the audience communicate with each other more equally. Gates, Anzaldua, and Campbell strive to add a new population to rhetoric and issues related to race, gender, and culture get more attention. Valuing participation, digital rhetoric in the 21st century may lead to a more democratic relationship between rhetor and audience. Hence, though I agree that modern rhetoric begins to question the nature of knowledge, classical rhetoric does not simply place rhetor and audience “in a clearly defined relationship with the world and with each other” (45). The more important distinction lies in that in modern rhetoric things like who can be a rhetor, who is the audience, and what kind of relationship they can have are rediscovered and redefined.             

Finally, it cannot be ignored that the scope of modern rhetoric is radically different from the scope of classical rhetoric. Though Lunsford and Ede emphasize that Aristotle’s persuasion cannot be understood in a narrow sense (44), which also includes interaction, modern rhetoric covers much more than persuasion. Richards sees rhetoric as exposition and communication; Burke introduces identification to rhetoric; Foucault and Bakhtin bring in discourse and dialogue; Gates, Anzaldua, and Campbell add race, gender, culture and identity. More interestingly, James Zappen’s “Digital Rhetoric: Toward an Integrated Theory” reveals a new field. The new digital media may lead to numerous new possibilities and change our current understanding of rhetoric. For example, the new goal of rhetoric can be “self-expression, participation, and creative collaboration” (321) as the new digital space gives individuals more freedom and results in a participatory culture. The traditional division between reader and author is also challenged because in video games, players can be authors and readers at the same time (322). And rhetoric begins to include “both the Web author’s choices of topics, arguments, sequences, and words and the reader’s processes of selection and semiosis” (322). Even interaction has a different meaning now: “interactions among multiple versions of our online selves and between these and our real selves” play an important role in identity formation, which points in a new direction for rhetoric. Therefore, though we may use the same word, it is clear that Aristotle’s interaction is essentially different from interaction in the digital age.

No comments:

Post a Comment